Rothbard - Society without State.pdf

(150 KB) Pobierz
Society without a State - Mises Institute
Society without a State - Mises Institute
1 z 11
http://www.mises.org/story/2429
Society without a State
By Murray N. Rothbard
Posted on 12/28/2006
[Subscribe at email services , tell others , or Digg this story.]
[Murray Rothbard delivered this talk 32 years ago today at the
American Society for Political and Legal Philosophy (ASPLP),
Washington, DC: December 28, 1974. It was first published in The
Libertarian Forum , volume 7.1, January 1975, available in PDF .]
In attempting to outline how a "society
without a state" Ï that is, an anarchist
society Ï might function successfully, I
would first like to defuse two common but
mistaken criticisms of this approach.
First, is the argument that in providing
for such defense or protection services
as courts, police, or even law itself, I am
simply smuggling the state back into
society in another form, and that
therefore the system I am both analyzing
and advocating is not "really" anarchism.
This sort of criticism can only involve us in an endless and arid dispute over
semantics. Let me say from the beginning that I define the state as that
institution which possesses one or both (almost always both) of the following
properties: (1) it acquires its income by the physical coercion known as
"taxation"; and (2) it asserts and usually obtains a coerced monopoly of the
provision of defense service (police and courts) over a given territorial area.
An institution not possessing either of these properties is not and cannot be,
in accordance with my definition, a state. On the other hand, I define
anarchist society as one where there is no legal possibility for coercive
aggression against the person or property of an individual. Anarchists oppose
the state because it has its very being in such aggression, namely, the
expropriation of private property through taxation, the coercive exclusion of
other providers of defense service from its territory, and all of the other
depredations and coercions that are built upon these twin foci of invasions of
individual rights.
Nor is our definition of the state arbitrary, for these two characteristics have
been possessed by what is generally acknowledged to be states throughout
recorded history. The state, by its use of physical coercion, has arrogated to
itself a compulsory monopoly of defense services over its territorial
jurisdiction. But it is certainly conceptually possible for such services to be
supplied by private, non-state institutions, and indeed such services have
historically been supplied by other organizations than the state. To be
opposed to the state is then not necessarily to be opposed to services that
have often been linked with it; to be opposed to the state does not
necessarily imply that we must be opposed to police protection, courts,
arbitration, the minting of money, postal service, or roads and highways.
Some anarchists have indeed been opposed to police and to all physical
coercion in defense of person and property, but this is not inherent in and is
fundamentally irrelevant to the anarchist position, which is precisely marked
by opposition to all physical coercion invasive of, or aggressing against,
person and property.
The crucial role of taxation may be seen in the fact that the state is the only
institution or organization in society which regularly and systematically
acquires its income through the use of physical coercion. All other individuals
or organizations acquire their income voluntarily, either (1) through the
voluntary sale of goods and services to consumers on the market, or (2)
through voluntary gifts or donations by members or other donors. If I cease
70352011.002.png 70352011.003.png
Society without a State - Mises Institute
2 z 11
http://www.mises.org/story/2429
or refrain from purchasing Wheaties on the market, the Wheaties producers
do not come after me with a gun or the threat of imprisonment to force me
to purchase; if I fail to join the American Philosophical Association, the
association may not force me to join or prevent me from giving up my
membership. Only the state can do so; only the state can confiscate my
property or put me in jail if I do not pay its tax tribute. Therefore, only the
state regularly exists and has its very being by means of coercive
depredations on private property.
Neither is it legitimate to challenge this sort of analysis by claiming that in
some other sense, the purchase of Wheaties or membership in the APA is in
some way "coercive." Anyone who is still unhappy with this use of the term
"coercion" can simply eliminate the word from this discussion and substitute
for it "physical violence or the threat thereof," with the only loss being in
literary style rather than in the substance of the argument. What anarchism
proposes to do, then, is to abolish the state, that is, to abolish the
regularized institution of aggressive coercion.
It need hardly be added that the state habitually builds upon its coercive
source of income by adding a host of other aggressions upon society, ranging
from economic controls to the prohibition of pornography to the compelling of
religious observance to the mass murder of civilians in organized warfare. In
short, the state, in the words of Albert Jay Nock, "claims and exercises a
monopoly of crime" over its territorial area.
The second criticism I would like to defuse before
beginning the main body of the paper is the
common charge that anarchists "assume that all
people are good" and that without the state no
crime would be committed. In short, that anarchism
assumes that with the abolition of the state a New
Anarchist Man will emerge, cooperative, humane,
and benevolent, so that no problem of crime will
then plague the society. I confess that I do not
understand the basis for this charge. Whatever
other schools of anarchism profess Ï and I do not
believe that they are open to the charge Ï I
certainly do not adopt this view. I assume with
most observers that mankind is a mixture of good and evil, of cooperative
and criminal tendencies. In my view, the anarchist society is one which
maximizes the tendencies for the good and the cooperative, while it
minimizes both the opportunity and the moral legitimacy of the evil and the
criminal. If the anarchist view is correct and the state is indeed the great
legalized and socially legitimated channel for all manner of antisocial crime Ï
theft, oppression, mass murder Ï on a massive scale, then surely the
abolition of such an engine of crime can do nothing but favor the good in
man and discourage the bad.
"Anyone who is
still unhappy with
this use of the
term coercion can
simply eliminate
the word from
this discussion
and substitute for
it physical
violence or the
threat thereofÈ."
A further point: in a profound sense, no social system, whether anarchist or
statist, can work at all unless most people are "good" in the sense that they
are not all hell-bent upon assaulting and robbing their neighbors. If everyone
were so disposed, no amount of protection, whether state or private, could
succeed in staving off chaos. Furthermore, the more that people are disposed
to be peaceful and not aggress against their neighbors, the more successfully
any social system will work, and the fewer resources will need to be devoted
to police protection. The anarchist view holds that, given the "nature of
man," given the degree of goodness or badness at any point in time,
anarchism will maximize the opportunities for the good and minimize the
channels for the bad. The rest depends on the values held by the individual
members of society. The only further point that need be made is that by
eliminating the living example and the social legitimacy of the massive
legalized crime of the state, anarchism will to a large extent promote
peaceful values in the minds of the public.
 
Society without a State - Mises Institute
3 z 11
http://www.mises.org/story/2429
We cannot of course deal here with the numerous arguments in favor of
anarchism or against the state, moral, political, and economic. Nor can we
take up the various goods and services now provided by the state and show
how private individuals and groups will be able to supply them far more
efficiently on the free market. Here we can only deal with perhaps the most
difficult area, the area where it is almost universally assumed that the state
must exist and act, even if it is only a "necessary evil" instead of a positive
good: the vital realm of defense or protection of person and property against
aggression. Surely, it is universally asserted, the state is at least vitally
necessary to provide police protection, the judicial resolution of disputes and
enforcement of contracts, and the creation of the law itself that is to be
enforced. My contention is that all of these admittedly necessary services of
protection can be satisfactorily and efficiently supplied by private persons
and institutions on the free market.
One important caveat before we begin the body of this paper: new proposals
such as anarchism are almost always gauged against the implicit assumption
that the present, or statist system works to perfection. Any lacunae or
difficulties with the picture of the anarchist society are considered net
liabilities, and enough to dismiss anarchism out of hand. It is, in short,
implicitly assumed that the state is doing its self-assumed job of protecting
person and property to perfection. We cannot here go into the reasons why
the state is bound to suffer inherently from grave flaws and inefficiencies in
such a task. All we need do now is to point to the black and unprecedented
record of the state through history: no combination of private marauders can
possibly begin to match the state's unremitting record of theft, confiscation,
oppression, and mass murder. No collection of Mafia or private bank robbers
can begin to compare with all the Hiroshimas, Dresdens, and Lidices and
their analogues through the history of mankind.
This point can be made more philosophically:
it is illegitimate to compare the merits of
anarchism and statism by starting with the
present system as the implicit given and then
critically examining only the anarchist
alternative. What we must do is to begin at
the zero point and then critically examine
both suggested alternatives. Suppose, for
example, that we were all suddenly dropped
down on the earth de novo and that we were
all then confronted with the question of what
societal arrangements to adopt. And suppose
then that someone suggested: "We are all bound to suffer from those of us
who wish to aggress against their fellow men. Let us then solve this problem
of crime by handing all of our weapons to the Jones family, over there, by
giving all of our ultimate power to settle disputes to that family. In that way,
with their monopoly of coercion and of ultimate decision making, the Jones
family will be able to protect each of us from each other." I submit that this
proposal would get very short shrift, except perhaps from the Jones family
themselves. And yet this is precisely the common argument for the existence
of the state. When we start from the zero point, as in the case of the Jones
family, the question of "who will guard the guardians?" becomes not simply
an abiding lacuna in the theory of the state but an overwhelming barrier to
its existence.
"In a profound sense,
no social system,
whether anarchist or
statist, can work at all
unless most people are
'good' in the sense that
they are not all
hell-bent upon
assaulting and robbing
their neighbors."
A final caveat: the anarchist is always at a disadvantage in attempting to
forecast the shape of the future anarchist society. For it is impossible for
observers to predict voluntary social arrangements, including the provision of
goods and services, on the free market. Suppose, for example, that this were
the year 1874 and that someone predicted that eventually there would be a
radio-manufacturing industry. To be able to make such a forecast
successfully, does he have to be challenged to state immediately how many
radio manufacturers there would be a century hence, how big they would be,
 
Society without a State - Mises Institute
4 z 11
http://www.mises.org/story/2429
where they would be located, what technology and marketing techniques
they would use, and so on? Obviously, such a challenge would make no
sense, and in a profound sense the same is true of those who demand a
precise portrayal of the pattern of protection activities on the market.
Anarchism advocates the dissolution of the state into social and market
arrangements, and these arrangements are far more flexible and less
predictable than political institutions. The most that we can do, then, is to
offer broad guidelines and perspectives on the shape of a projected anarchist
society.
One important point to make here is that the advance of modern technology
makes anarchistic arrangements increasingly feasible. Take, for example, the
case of lighthouses, where it is often charged that it is unfeasible for private
lighthouse operators to row out to each ship to charge it for use of the light.
Apart from the fact that this argument ignores the successful existence of
private lighthouses in earlier days, as in England in the eighteenth century,
another vital consideration is that modern electronic technology makes
charging each ship for the light far more feasible. Thus, the ship would have
to have paid for an electronically controlled beam which could then be
automatically turned on for those ships which had paid for the service.
Let us turn now to the problem of how disputes Ï in particular disputes over
alleged violations of person and property Ï would be resolved in an anarchist
society. First, it should be noted that all disputes involve two parties: the
plaintiff, the alleged victim of the crime or tort and the defendant, the
alleged aggressor. In many cases of broken contract, of course, each of the
two parties alleging that the other is the culprit is at the same time a plaintiff
and a defendant.
An important point to remember is that any society, be it statist or anarchist,
has to have some way of resolving disputes that will gain a majority
consensus in society. There would be no need for courts or arbitrators if
everyone were omniscient and knew instantaneously which persons were
guilty of any given crime or violation of contract. Since none of us is
omniscient, there has to be some method of deciding who is the criminal or
lawbreaker which will gain legitimacy; in short, whose decision will be
accepted by the great majority of the public.
In the first place, a dispute may be resolved
voluntarily between the two parties themselves,
either unaided or with the help of a third
mediator. This poses no problem, and will
automatically be accepted by society at large. It
is so accepted even now, much less in a society
imbued with the anarchistic values of peaceful
cooperation and agreement. Secondly and
similarly, the two parties, unable to reach
agreement, may decide to submit voluntarily to
the decision of an arbitrator. This agreement may arise either after a dispute
has arisen, or be provided for in advance in the original contract. Again,
there is no problem in such an arrangement gaining legitimacy. Even in the
present statist era, the notorious inefficiency and coercive and cumbersome
procedures of the politically run government courts has led increasing
numbers of citizens to turn to voluntary and expert arbitration for a speedy
and harmonious settling of disputes.
"New proposals such
as anarchism are
almost always
gauged against the
implicit assumption
that the present, or
statist system works
to perfection."
Thus, William C. Wooldridge has written that
Arbitration has grown to proportions that make the courts a
secondary recourse in many areas and completely superfluous in
others. The ancient fear of the courts that arbitration would "oust"
them of their jurisdiction has been fulfilled with a vengeance the
common-law judges probably never anticipated. Insurance
 
Society without a State - Mises Institute
5 z 11
http://www.mises.org/story/2429
companies adjust over fifty thousand claims a year among
themselves through arbitration, and the American Arbitration
Association (AAA), with headquarters in New York and twenty-five
regional offices across the country, last year conducted over
twenty-two thousand arbitrations. Its twenty-three thousand
associates available to serve as arbitrators may outnumber the
total number of judicial personnel È in the United StatesÈ. Add to
this the unknown number of individuals who arbitrate disputes
within particular industries or in particular localities, without
formal AAA affiliation, and the quantitatively secondary role of
official courts begins to be apparent. [1]
Wooldridge adds the important point that, in addition to the speed of
arbitration procedures vis--vis the courts, the arbitrators can proceed as
experts in disregard of the official government law; in a profound sense,
then, they serve to create a voluntary body of private law. "In other words,"
states Wooldridge, "the system of extralegal, voluntary courts has progressed
hand in hand with a body of private law; the rules of the state are
circumvented by the same process that circumvents the forums established
for the settlement of disputes over those rulesÈ. In short, a private
agreement between two people, a bilateral "law," has supplanted the official
law. The writ of the sovereign has cease to run, and for it is substituted a
rule tacitly or explicitly agreed to by the parties. Wooldridge concludes that
"if an arbitrator can choose to ignore a penal damage rule or the statute of
limitations applicable to the claim before him (and it is generally conceded
that he has that power), arbitration can be viewed as a practically
revolutionary instrument for self-liberation from the lawÈ." [2]
It may be objected that arbitration only works
successfully because the courts enforce the award of
the arbitrator. Wooldridge points out, however, that
arbitration was unenforceable in the American courts
before 1920, but that this did not prevent voluntary
arbitration from being successful and expanding in
the United States and in England. He points,
furthermore, to the successful operations of merchant
courts since the Middle Ages, those courts which
successfully developed the entire body of the law
merchant. None of those courts possessed the power
of enforcement. He might have added the private
courts of shippers which developed the body of
admiralty law in a similar way.
$15
"The idea that the
state is needed to
make law is as
much a myth as
that the state is
needed to supply
postal or police
services."
How then did these private, "anarchistic," and
voluntary courts ensure the acceptance of their
decisions? By the method of social ostracism, and by
the refusal to deal any further with the offending
merchant. This method of voluntary "enforcement,"
indeed proved highly successful. Wooldridge writes that "the merchants'
courts were voluntary, and if a man ignored their judgment, he could not be
sent to jailÈ. Nevertheless, it is apparent that È [their] decisions were
generally respected even by the losers; otherwise people would never have
used them in the first placeÈ. Merchants made their courts work simply by
agreeing to abide by the results. The merchant who broke the understanding
would not be sent to jail, to be sure, but neither would he long continue to be
a merchant, for the compliance exacted by his fellows È proved if anything
more effective than physical coercion." [3] Nor did this voluntary method fail
to work in modern times. Wooldridge writes that it was precisely in the years
before 1920, when arbitration awards could not be enforced in the courts,
that arbitration caught on and developed a following in the
American mercantile community. Its popularity, gained at a time
 
70352011.001.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin