Heidegger And The Political.pdf

(85 KB) Pobierz
4Ptq2000.vp:CorelVentura 7.0
Blitz / HEIDEGGER AND THE POLITICAL
HEIDEGGER AND THE POLITICAL
MARK BLITZ
Claremont McKenna College
I
Heidegger and the Political is the kind of topic that Heidegger did not like.
He always claimed to be uninterested in writing an ethics, an aesthetics, or
any other book in one of philosophy’s usual fields. 1 After all, one of his goals
was to put into question the ordinary divisions and subject matter of philoso-
phy. What is the unity from which these splits come about in the first place,
and how crisply articulated are they? Indeed, are even the usual terms through
which we study these subjects—the division, say, between subject and object
or between what something is and that something is—well grounded and
articulated? The fields of philosophy and the concepts we use to explore them
arise from and occur within this broader unity and ground, and it is to this that
Heidegger wanted to attend.
Heidegger also was wary of “Heidegger and Politics” because he did not
enjoy discussions that touched on his support for the Nazis, and how, one
might ask, could any discussion of his politics fail to do just that? Although
Heidegger’s amazingly subtle understanding of “is” usually enabled him to
say what his support of the Nazis “was” without lying, there was much that he
would have preferred to remain covered up. Heidegger by and large told the
truth, but not the whole truth. 2
Still, we are justified in examining Heidegger and politics on grounds that
stem from Heidegger himself and not merely from our external interests,
however urgent. Heidegger claimed from the beginning to the end of his work
that a unique connection exists between man and being. In one way or
another, being and man find their home in each other, although men necessar-
ily and at the same time have a wandering eye. 3 The openness of human
beings to being, and thus to beings as a whole and as such, is the basis for
every other characteristic and activity. Moods, discourse, ordinary and extra-
ordinary private and public attachments, art, work, philosophy, and states-
POLITICAL THEORY, Vol. 28 No. 2, April 2000 167-196
© 2000 Sage Publications, Inc.
167
POLITICAL THEORY / April 2000
81608312.001.png 81608312.002.png
168
POLITICAL THEORY / April 2000
manship are all grounded in this essential relationship. Now, if we were to ask
earlier thinkers to name a subject whose heart is in one sense man’s soul and
in another sense the being of all the other beings but that is, most of all, about
how the powers of man and nature (and studying them) belong together,
political philosophy would be as likely an answer as any other. It would not be
the only answer, but it would certainly be a plausible one for Aristotle and
Plato. The city and its laws in a certain sense are about or include everything,
especially when we remember that philosophers and poets are citizens, what-
ever else they are. 4
Heidegger’s discussion of man and being, moreover, always includes ele-
ments that are as practical as they are theoretical. This is obvious in Being and
Time and the lectures preceding and immediately following it. In his later
publications too, however, he also discusses what “in any other man” we
would call practical issues and phenomena: action, the gods, the polis and its
regime, the will, history, National Socialism, Americanism, simple imple-
ments, and leadership, among others. 5 Several of these topics are essential
and not just discussed by the by. Again, were we to ask where in the past such
issues are discussed, practical philosophy—rhetoric, ethics, and, above all,
political philosophy—would be a plausible answer.
So, because Heidegger deals philosophically with many practical phe-
nomena and because his basic understanding puts man and being in each
other’s center, studying “Heidegger and the Political” is not only a product of
our current academic divisions or of our concern about his Nazism. Studying
what is political, as well as studying other issues from the point of view of
how they enter into man’s political rule, is a sensible way to come to under-
stand Heidegger generally.
Of course, Heidegger claims he is not engaged in practical philosophy,
and he calls nothing that he does political philosophy. And he mentions many
usual topics of political philosophy only glancingly, if at all. Thus, whatever
similarities in subject matter we might find, he would argue that his attention
is directed to a different place. In his later works, he claims to be oriented to
something other than what attracted the attention of any of the previous phi-
losophers: he is now considering what, qua philosophers, they needed to
ignore. In Being and Time and the accompanying works, his claim is not so
radical, but the intention of his thought is the same—namely, one that is
pointed to an area that previous philosophers took for granted.
Nonetheless, unless we are completely convinced that what these matters
“are” is to be located in the realm that Heidegger uncovers and that what he
discusses is a priori to the causes and grounds of human study and affairs,
then we should not take for granted the apparent priority or, at least, incom-
Blitz / HEIDEGGER AND THE POLITICAL
169
mensurability of his subject with the philosophical study of human things.
The subject of politics (and its philosophical study) is central not because it is
an interesting area to which one would like to apply Heidegger’s thought but
because it is a different way to consider the status of what Heidegger uncov-
ers. Given that a new view of practical affairs is important in his work, and
given especially that if neither man (or philosophical “psychology” or con-
sciousness) nor “being” (or ontology or philosophy of “nature” or objectiv-
ity) but something about their correlation is the ground of things, then politi-
cal philosophy (and here we think especially of The Republic ) is a likely
alternative or competitor. Studying Heidegger and the political is an espe-
cially fruitful way to challenge or confront him because politics as a subject
and the ways in which political philosophers have studied it suggest imma-
nent limits and alternatives to Heidegger’s analysis.
Heidegger, of course, did not say this, and his silence should give us pause.
Indeed, it would be fairly easy for a Heideggerian to imitate how Heidegger
might try to show that political philosophy is limited by being merely meta-
physical, even if it is a place where the commonality of man and being is
genuinely established, or that in fact it largely borrows from metaphysics and
establishes nothing by itself, or that it is for the most part merely technical
and useful. But our real pause should come from recognizing that Heideg-
ger’s investigations and political or practical philosophy cannot be simply
assimilated, whatever the similarity in subject and purpose. This will enable
us to see where exactly the transformations are that Heidegger seeks to effect,
what they are, and what their merit is. Nonetheless, and most crucially, we
should not become hesitant because we assume in advance that Heidegger
has in fact uncovered a new, comprehensive, and significant territory in
which everything else must take its place.
II
To confront Heidegger properly and to place correctly his own explicit
remarks about “the political,” we must consider Heidegger’s own purpose
and goal. This means that we must explore what Heidegger is seeking when
he seeks “being” because this is the (usually explicit) subject of all his lec-
tures and publications. I will discuss this in several ways, hoping in the end to
have generated some understanding.
One way to approach Heidegger’s “being” is to see that he is seeking the
correlative to what is most distinctively human (and in this sense, he also
seeks what is distinctively human). What is our language as such, and what is
170
POLITICAL THEORY / April 2000
it about; what are our feelings as such, and what are they about? What are
these and what do they deal with when they are considered simply in them-
selves and are not considered to be caused or brought about by something
alien to them such as mechanical motions? What exactly is the distinctive
freedom that is aligned with these traits, and how “are” other things as they
matter to or are dealt with by our freely exercised characteristics? What are
the elements in things (including ourselves) that, although we do not create
them, can be what they are only when we allow them to be?
What is distinctive about us in this way is said to be our “being,” and what
is correlated to it is what other things are, beings as such, beings in their
being, including our own being as one of the things that we understand.
Beings in their being, as opposed to concrete characteristics that they have in
their being and to which we respond, are the proper and distinctive human
“objects.” And our proper and distinctive humanity, what our feelings and
language do as such and are about is to see, articulate, and respond to this
being. To see beings “as such” is to see them in their being, and to see them in
their being is precisely to see this “as such.” The ability to see beings as such
defines all men and is not the exclusive preserve of philosophers or poets,
although there is something special about “creators.” 6
III
Why does Heidegger claim that our being, that which uniquely defines our
traits and characteristics, is our relation to beings as such, including our own
being? One answer is that something’s “being,” how it “is,” stands for what is
unavoidable about it. Being is that about us and things that is always already
there, whatever else is. (Heidegger, of course, has a new understanding of
what this unavoidability is and how it happens.) It is embedded in any demar-
cation whatsoever, including the demarcation of ourselves. 7 Any way in
which we see or deal with something as this or that requires that we already
have articulated it as this thing that it is and not something else. A hammer
can be used as a hammer only because we first see that it is a hammer, which
in its case means only because we have already articulated a realm of rele-
vance and significance within which things—in this case the hammer—can
be ready for use.
This “a priori” relation to beings as such might seem too primitive and ele-
mentary to count as what we are distinctively, let alone primarily. In a sense,
however, all philosophy makes this claim. For Plato, Aristotle, and (accord-
ing to Heidegger) the pre-Socratics, what something is is its nature, what
Blitz / HEIDEGGER AND THE POLITICAL
171
emerges in the thing on its own or, better, the thing as emerging on its own.
Our own being is to understand things, including ourselves, in their nature.
The fullest understanding (and, therefore, the fullest natural humanity) is phi-
losophy, which sees nature as such. Rather than being guided by an opinion
about justice, for instance, rather than being guided by a view that sees justice
only partially (but is just only to the degree that it sees justice at all), the phi-
losopher seeks to be guided by what justice is simply by nature. This natural
justice (and the other things that are first by nature) already lies in advance in
any particular thing that is in any way just. Alternatively, if what distin-
guishes human beings from everything else is “consciousness” or awareness
(or awareness that is aware of itself being aware of other things or that is
aware of itself being aware of itself), things as they are for that original aware-
ness are how they are simply. Otherwise, they will not have been articulated
in terms of what is most permanent and unavoidable. It is only over against an
ineluctable (self) consciousness that things could stand there in a presence
that allows them to be stably articulated for our own stable fullness; if we did
not see them in terms of our consciousness, our approach to them would be
truncated and subject to change, as would our full freeing of ourselves. As it
turns out, to release beings fully to our consciousness is to release objects that
are fully secured by our subjective consciousness; most significant here is the
release of objects understood as causes and effects within a fully secured
methodological approach. In this way, what is simply objective is what it is in
terms of a subjectively controlled and mastered method that sets out in
advance the genuine being (objectivity) in terms of which things can be
discovered.
IV
One might suggest (as the above discussion indicates) that what Heideg-
ger seeks already has been found and articulated. Our free stance toward a
truth of mathematics is precisely to articulate it mathematically, to know it
through proof rather than reducing its truth and our awareness of its truth to
psychological, sociological, historical, mechanical, or chemical origins. We
are ourselves in knowing it as it is. In what way is this (and its analogues in
other areas) insufficient for Heidegger?
Heidegger would hardly deny that science or philosophy is oriented to
what things are as such. But they take for granted a broader horizon within
which their own understanding occurs. Consciousness and nature, for exam-
ple, mean and matter something to us only within a horizon more original
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin