[Mathematics] [Philosophy] - Russell, Bertrand - Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (1924)(1).pdf

(496 KB) Pobierz
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Bertrand%20Russell.1924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Bertrand%20Russell.1924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html
Library of Philosophy.
EDITED BY J. H. MUIRHEAD, LL.D.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL
PHILOSOPHY
-i-
[This page intentionally left blank.]
-ii-
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL
PHILOSOPHY
BY BERTRAND RUSSELL
LONDON: GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN, LTD.
NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN CO.
-iii-
First published May 1919 Second Edition April 1920 Reprinted May 1924
All rights reserved Printed in Great Britain by NEILL & Co., LTD., EDINBURGH.
-iv-
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Ber...924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html (1 of 167)15/11/2006 8:03:38
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Bertrand%20Russell.1924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html
PREFACE
THIS book is intended essentially as an "Introduction," and does not aim at giving an exhaustive
discussion of the problems with which it deals. It seemed desirable to set forth certain results,
hitherto only available to those who have mastered logical symbolism, in a form offering the
minimum of difficulty to the beginner. The utmost endeavour has been made to avoid dogmatism
on such questions as are still open to serious doubt, and this endeavour has to some extent
dominated the choice of topics considered. The beginnings of mathematical logic are less
definitely known than its later portions, but are of at least equal philosophical interest. Much of
what is set forth in the following chapters is not properly to be called "philosophy," though the
matters concerned were included in philosophy so long as no satisfactory science of them existed.
The nature of infinity and continuity, for example, belonged in former days to philosophy, but
belongs now to mathematics. Mathematical philosophy , in the strict sense, cannot, perhaps, be
held to include such definite scientific results as have been obtained in this region; the philosophy
of mathematics will naturally be expected to deal with questions on the frontier of knowledge, as
to which comparative certainty is not yet attained. But speculation on such questions is hardly
likely to be fruitful unless the more scientific parts of the principles of mathematics are known. A
book dealing with those parts may, therefore, claim to be an introduction to mathematical
philosophy, though it can hardly claim, except where it steps outside its province, to be actually
dealing with a part of philosophy. It does deal,
-v-
however, with a body of knowledge which, to those who accept it, appears to invalidate much
traditional philosophy, and even a good deal of what is current in the present day. In this way, as
well as by its bearing on still unsolved problems, mathematical logic is relevant to philosophy.
For this reason, as well as on account of the intrinsic importance of the subject, some purpose may
be served by a succinct account of the main results of mathematical logic in a form requiring
neither a knowledge of mathematics nor an aptitude for mathematical symbolism. Here, however,
as elsewhere, the method is more important than the results, from the point of view of further
research; and the method cannot well be explained within the framework of such a book as the
following. It is to be hoped that some readers may be sufficiently interested to advance to a study
of the method by which mathematical logic can be made helpful in investigating the traditional
problems of philosophy. But that is a topic with which the following pages have not attempted to
deal.
BERTRAND RUSSELL.
-vi-
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Ber...924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html (2 of 167)15/11/2006 8:03:38
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Bertrand%20Russell.1924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html
EDITOR'S NOTE
THOSE who, relying on the distinction between Mathematical Philosophy and the Philosophy of
Mathematics, think that this book is out of place in the present Library, may be referred to what
the author himself says on this head in the Preface. It is not necessary to agree with what he there
suggests as to the readjustment of the field of philosophy by the transference from it to
mathematics of such problems as those of class, continuity, infinity, in order to perceive the
bearing of the definitions and discussions that follow on the work of "traditional philosophy." If
philosophers cannot consent to relegate the criticism of these categories to any of the special
sciences, it is essential, at any rate, that they should know the precise meaning that the science of
mathematics, in which these concepts play so large a part, assigns to them. If, on the other hand,
there be mathematicians to whom these definitions and discussions seem to be an elaboration and
complication of the simple, it may be well to remind them from the side of philosophy that here,
as elsewhere, apparent simplicity may conceal a complexity which it is the business of somebody,
whether philosopher or mathematician, or, like the author of this volume, both in one, to unravel.
-vii-
CONTENTS
PREFACE
v
EDITOR'S NOTE
vii
1. THE SERIES OF NATURAL NUMBERS
1
2. DEFINITION OF NUMBER
11
3. FINITUDE AND MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
20
4. THE DEFINITION OF ORDER
29
5. KINDS OF RELATIONS
42
6. SIMILARITY OF RELATIONS
52
7. RATIONAL, REAL, AND COMPLEX NUMBERS
63
8. INFINITE CARDINAL NUMBERS
77
9. INFINITE SERIES AND ORDINALS
89
10. LIMITS AND CONTINUITY
97
11. LIMITS AND CONTINUITY OF FUNCTIONS
107
12. SELECTIONS AND THE MULTIPLICATIVE AXIOM
117
13. THE AXIOM OF INFINITY AND LOGICAL TYPES
131
14. INCOMPATIBILITY AND THE THEORY OF DEDUCTION
144
15. PROPOSITIONAL FUNCTIONS
155
16. DESCRIPTIONS
167
17. CLASSES
181
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Ber...924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html (3 of 167)15/11/2006 8:03:38
23132027.001.png
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Bertrand%20Russell.1924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html
18. MATHEMATICS AND LOGIC
194
INDEX
207
-viii-
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy
CHAPTER I
THE SERIES OF NATURAL NUMBERS
MATHEMATICS is a study which, when we start from its most familiar portions, may be
pursued in either of two opposite directions. The more familiar direction is constructive, towards
gradually increasing complexity: from integers to fractions, real numbers, complex numbers; from
addition and multiplication to differentiation and integration, and on to higher mathematics. The
other direction, which is less familiar, proceeds, by analysing, to greater and greater abstractness
and logical simplicity; instead of asking what can be defined and deduced from what is assumed
to begin with, we ask instead what more general ideas and principles can be found, in terms of
which what was our starting-point can be defined or deduced. It is the fact of pursuing this
opposite direction that characterises mathematical philosophy as opposed to ordinary
mathematics. But it should be understood that the distinction is one, not in the subject matter, but
in the state of mind of the investigator. Early Greek geometers, passing from the empirical rules of
Egyptian land-surveying to the general propositions by which those rules were found to be
justifiable, and thence to Euclid's axioms and postulates, were engaged in mathematical
philosophy, according to the above definition; but when once the axioms and postulates had been
reached, their deductive employment, as we find it in Euclid, belonged to mathematics in the
-1-
ordinary sense. The distinction between mathematics and mathematical philosophy is one which
depends upon the interest inspiring the research, and upon the stage which the research has
reached; not upon the propositions with which the research is concerned.
We may state the same distinction in another way. The most obvious and easy things in
mathematics are not those that come logically at the beginning; they are things that, from the point
of view of logical deduction, come somewhere in the middle. Just as the easiest bodies to see are
those that are neither very near nor very far, neither very small nor very great, so the easiest
conceptions to grasp are those that are neither very complex nor very simple (using "simple" in a
logical sense). And as we need two sorts of instruments, the telescope and the microscope, for the
enlargement of our visual powers, so we need two sorts of instruments for the enlargement of our
logical powers, one to take us forward to the higher mathematics, the other to take us backward to
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Ber...924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html (4 of 167)15/11/2006 8:03:38
 
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Bertrand%20Russell.1924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html
the logical foundations of the things that we are inclined to take for granted in mathematics. We
shall find that by analysing our ordinary mathematical notions we acquire fresh insight, new
powers, and the means of reaching whole new mathematical subjects by adopting fresh lines of
advance after our backward journey. It is the purpose of this book to explain mathematical
philosophy simply and untechnically, without enlarging upon those portions which are so doubtful
or difficult that an elementary treatment is scarcely possible. A full treatment will be found in
Principia Mathematica ; 1 the treatment in the present volume is intended merely as an
introduction.
To the average educated person of the present day, the obvious starting-point of mathematics
would be the series of whole numbers,
1, 2, 3, 4, . . . etc.
____________________
1 Cambridge University Press, vol. i., 1910; vol. ii., 1911; vol. iii., 1913. By Whitehead and
Russell.
-2-
Probably only a person with some mathematical knowledge would think of beginning with 0
instead of with 1, but we will presume this degree of knowledge; we will take as our startingpoint
the series :
0, 1, 2, 3, . . . n, n+1, . . .
and it is this series that we shall mean when we speak of the is series of natural numbers."
It is only at a high stage of civilisation that we could take this series as our starting-point. It must
have required many ages to discover that a brace of pheasants and a couple of days were both
instances of the number 2: the degree of abstraction involved is far from easy. And the discovery
that 1 is a number must have been difficult. As for 0, it is a very recent addition; the Greeks and
Romans had no such digit. If we had been embarking upon mathematical philosophy in earlier
days, we should have had to start with something less abstract than the series of natural numbers,
which we should reach as a stage on our backward journey. When the logical foundations of
mathematics have grown more familiar, we shall be able to start further back, at what is now a late
stage in our analysis. But for the moment the natural numbers seem to represent what is easiest
and most familiar in mathematics.
But though familiar, they are not understood. Very few people are prepared with a definition of
what is meant by "number," or "0," or "1." It is not very difficult to see that, starting from 0, any
file:///C|/Archivos%20de%20programa/eMule/Incoming/Ber...924.Introduction%20to%20Mathematical%20Philosophy.html (5 of 167)15/11/2006 8:03:38
23132027.002.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin