Emotions as metarepresentational states of mind11.pdf

(250 KB) Pobierz
Emotions as metarepresentational states of mind: Naturalizing the belief–desire theory of emotion
Available online at www.sciencedirect.com
Cognitive Systems Research 10 (2009) 6–20
www.elsevier.com/locate/cogsys
Emotions as metarepresentational states of mind: Naturalizing
the belief–desire theory of emotion
Action Editor: Jonathan Gratch
Rainer Reisenzein
Institute of Psychology, University of Greifswald, Franz-Mehring-Straße 47, 17487 Greifswald, Germany
Received 14 September 2007; accepted 31 March 2008
Available online 18 June 2008
Abstract
Describes the outlines of a computational explication of the belief–desire theory of emotion, a variant of cognitive emotion theory.
According to the proposed explication, a core subset of emotions including surprise are nonconceptual products of hardwired mecha-
nisms whose primary function is to subserve the monitoring and updating of the central representational system of humans, the
belief–desire system. The posited emotion-producing mechanisms are analogous to sensory transducers; however, instead of sensing
the world, they sense the state of the belief–desire system and signal important changes in this system, in particular the fulfillment
and frustration of desires and the confirmation and disconfirmation of beliefs. Because emotions represent this information about the
state of the representational system in a nonconceptual format, emotions are nonconceptual metarepresentations. It is argued that this
theory of emotions provides for a deepened understanding of the role of emotions in cognitive systems and solves several problems of
psychological emotion theory.
2008 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
Keywords: Emotion; Belief–desire theory; Metacognition; Affective computing; BDI
What are emotions, and what is their function in the
economy of the mind? I propose that at least for a core sub-
set of emotions including surprise, these questions can be
answered as follows: Emotions are nonconceptual outputs
of hardwired mechanisms whose primary function is to
subserve the monitoring and updating of the central repre-
sentational system of humans, the belief–desire system.
This theory of emotions, which closely connects emotions
to the monitoring and updating of representations and
assigns them important epistemic functions—in holding
that they convey to agents important information about
their own representational system—may at first appear
unusual. In fact, however, it can be argued that this view
of emotions is already implicit in the currently dominant
theories of emotion, the cognitive emotion theories (for
an overview, see Scherer, Schorr, & Johnstone, 2001 ).
For these theories assume implicitly that emotions are clo-
sely tied to changes in beliefs and desires; and at least some
of them explicitly attribute to emotions an informational
function (e.g., Ortony, Clore, & Collins, 1988 ). In fact,
the computational model of emotions sketched in this arti-
cle is an attempt to ‘‘naturalize” (to integrate into the
scientific picture; Dretske, 1995 ) a particular version of
cognitive emotion theory, the belief–desire theory of emo-
tion (BDTE).
The motivation for this attempt was the observation
that many important issues are still controversial among
cognitive emotion theorists (see also, Reisenzein, 2001,
2006a ) and the belief that, to resolve these issues, it is
indispensable to consider the cognitive architecture that
underlies emotions. Although cognitive emotion theorists
are agreed that (most) emotions presuppose cognitions,
they differ on exactly which cognitions are necessary for
1389-0417/$ - see front matter 2008 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.cogsys.2008.03.001
782465562.001.png
R. Reisenzein / Cognitive Systems Research 10 (2009) 6–20
7
emotions (e.g., factual beliefs, evaluative beliefs, or both)
and in which sense they are necessary (e.g., are they
required as causes or components of emotions); whether
and in what sense emotions also presuppose desires; how
the cognitive processes that generate emotions look like
in detail; what the emotion itself is (i.e., how it is to be the-
oretically defined) and which functions emotion have; how
emotions relate to emotional experiences; what accounts
for the distinctive quality and the intensity of emotional
experiences; and how the object-directedness of emotions
can be explained. The theory of emotion proposed in this
article gives or at least sketches answers to all these ques-
tion and thus offers a coherent picture of the emotional
mind. At the same time, the theory seeks to preserve the
central insights of cognitive emotion theories but to avoid
objections that have been raised against them.
The article has three parts. In the first part, I give an
overview of BDTE. In the second part, I sketch a compu-
tational model of BDTE. In the third part, I present argu-
ments in favor of the proposed computational explication
of BDTE.
taken to be basic kinds of mental states—modes of relating
to objects—that cannot be reduced to one another. To
mention but one difference between the two: Beliefs, but
not desires, can be true or false; desires, but not beliefs,
can be satisfied or frustrated (e.g., Green, 1992 ). As dis-
cussed in the next section, the distinction between beliefs
and desires is ultimately based on the fundamentally differ-
ent functional roles that these mental states play in the
economy of the mind.
BDTE theorists differ, among other issues, on the ques-
tion of the precise sense in which emotions are ‘‘products
of” beliefs and desires. Whereas some regard beliefs and
desires as components of emotions (see Green, 1992 , for fur-
ther discussion), I follow Meinong (1906) in assuming that
beliefs and desires are the causes of the emotion, which is a
mental state of its own. Presupposing this ‘‘causalist” inter-
pretation of BDTE, its basic assumption can be stated
more precisely as follows: At least a core subset of the men-
tal states presystematically subsumed under the category
‘‘emotion” are reactions to the cognized actual (e.g., happi-
ness, unhappiness) or potential (e.g., hope, fear) fulfillment
or frustration of desires plus, in some cases (e.g., Surprise,
disappointment), confirmations or disconfirmations of
beliefs.
To illustrate BDTE, consider the case of Mary, who
feels happy that Mr. Schroiber was elected chancellor.
(For the time being, I identify emotions with emotional
experiences. A distinction between the two is drawn later
in the computational explication of the theory.) According
to BDTE, Mary feels happy about Mr. Schroiber’s election
if Mary (a) comes to (firmly) believe that Schroiber was
elected and (b) desires this state of affairs. In slightly more
detail, the process of emotion generation, here illustrated
for happiness, typically looks as shown in Fig. 1 . First,
the person comes to desire some state of affairs or proposi-
tion p. 1 For example, Mary acquires the desire that Schro-
iber is elected chancellor. Some time later—as a result of
new information acquired through the senses, communica-
tion from others, or inference from existing beliefs—the
person acquires the belief that p obtains. For example,
when watching the news on TV, Mary comes to believe
that Schroiber was, indeed, elected chancellor. Thereupon,
the emotion occurs: Mary now feels happy or pleased that
Schroiber was elected. 2 Note that the belief and desire are
connected to the emotion not only as cause to effect, but
also semantically: The belief that p, the desire for p and
happiness about p concern a common topic, they all refer
1. The belief–desire theory of emotion
The belief–desire theory of emotion belongs to the
broader class of cognitive emotion theories represented,
for example, by the theories of Arnold (1960), Frijda
(1986), Lazarus (1991), Oatley and Johnson-Laird (1987),
Ortony et al. (1988), and Scherer (2001) in psychology;
and those of Kenny (1963), Lyons (1980), Nussbaum
(2001), and Solomon (1976) in philosophy (for reviews,
see Ellsworth & Scherer, 2003; Goldie, 2007 ). Cognitive
emotion theories have come to dominate psychological
and philosophical theorizing on emotions during the past
two decades, and they also form the basis of most existing
computational models of emotion (e.g., Elliott, 1992;
Gratch & Marsella, 2004; Neal Reilly, 1996; Staller & Pet-
ta, 2001 ). As a distinct type of emotion theory within the
cognitive approach to emotions, BDTE has been primarily
promoted by philosophers (e.g., Davis, 1981; Green, 1992;
Marks, 1982; Searle, 1983 ; and for an early version, Mei-
nong, 1894, 1906 [summary in Reisenzein, 2006a ]). Propo-
nents of BDTE in psychology include Roseman (1979) and
Miceli and Castelfranchi (1997, 2007) .
1.1. Basic assumptions of BDTE
The conceptual framework of BDTE is the same as that
of the philosophical belief–desire theory of action (e.g.,
Bratman, 1987; Mele, 1992 ) which inspired the BDI
(belief–desire–intention) approach to artificial agents
( Bratman, Israel, & Pollack, 1988 ). Analogous to the
belief–desire theory of action, which holds that actions
are the product of cognitive or informational states
(beliefs) and motivational states (desires), BDTE posits
that emotions are the product of cognitions (beliefs) and
motives (desires). In this analysis, beliefs and desires are
1 This is the philosophical usage of ‘‘proposition”.Psychologists
typically use the term to denote a sentence in a language-like mental
representation system that represents states of affairs (e.g., Kintsch, 1988;
Anderson & Lebiere, 1998 ).
2 The converse temporal sequence is possible also. Mary may first learn
that Schroiber was elected chancellor, and come to desire that state of
affairs only later, when she reads about Schroiber’s political program. In
this case, the desire is cognized as being fulfilled as soon as it is formed,
resulting again in Mary’s happiness about Schroiber’s election.
8
R. Reisenzein / Cognitive Systems Research 10 (2009) 6–20
Desire(p)
elected (i.e., believes with uncertainty that p obtains);
whereas Mary fears at t that Schroiber is elected if she
diswants him to be elected but is uncertain whether or
not he will be elected. Mary is surprised at t that Schroiber
is elected chancellor if she up to t believed he would not be
elected ( : p) and at t comes to firmly believe that he was
elected (p). Mary is disappointed at time t that Schroiber
is not elected chancellor if she desires him to be elected
and up to t believed that this was likely or at least possible,
but at t comes to firmly believe that he was not elected ( : p).
Finally, Mary is relieved that Schroiber is not elected chan-
cellor if she diswants him to be elected and up to t believed
that this was at least possible, but at t comes to firmly
believe that he was not elected.
Although the emotions listed in Table 1 still comprise
only a small subset of the emotions distinguished in ordin-
ary language, from the perspective of BDTE they are basic
forms. Happiness and unhappiness are the emotional reac-
tions to the cognized actual fulfillment versus frustration of
desires; hope and fear to their cognized possible fulfillment
versus frustration. Surprise is the general emotional reac-
tion to belief-disconfirmation; if it co-occurs with desire–
fulfillment, it is pleasant surprise; if it co-occurs with desire
frustration, it is unpleasant surprise. Disappointment and
relief are the emotional reactions to the unexpected
(belief-disconfirming) nonoccurrence of desire fulfillment
versus frustration, respectively.
The diversity and complexity of humans’ emotional life
gets into the picture primarily, if not exclusively, via the
objects or contents of the beliefs and desires that give rise
to emotions. In other words, the diversity and complexity
of human emotions is due to the fact that humans have
diverse and complex desires and beliefs. In particular, as
a highly social species (e.g., Richerson & Boyd, 1998 ),
humans have desires that concern not only their own wel-
fare, but also the welfare of others, as well as their own
and others’ compliance with social and moral norms.
Accordingly, other-regarding emotions, such as joy for
another, Schadenfreude, pity,andenvy can be analyzed as
forms of happiness or unhappiness about, respectively, a
desired or undesired state of affairs p that concerns the
positive or negative fate of another person (e.g., Meinong,
1894; Ortony et al., 1988 ). The classical ‘‘moral emotions”,
such as guilt and indignation on the negative side, and
pride or moral elevation on the positive side, can be incor-
porated into the belief–desire framework by assuming that
the content of the desire (the desired proposition) in these
cases is the compliance of oneself or another person with
a social or moral norm (e.g., Ortony et al., 1988; Staller
& Petta, 2001 ). In addition, BDTE can be extended to
cover ‘‘fantasy emotions” (i.e., emotional reactions to
anticipated or counterfactually imagined states of affairs),
by positing that these emotions are based on assumptions
rather than beliefs ( Meinong, 1910; Reisenzein, Meyer, &
Sch¨ tzwohl, 2003 ). In the computational model of BDTE
described later, this would mean to add a ‘‘pretense store”
to the cognitive architecture (see Nichols & Stich, 2000 ).
Happiness(p)
Belief(p)
New
information
Fig. 1. Basic belief–desire analysis of emotions.
to p ( Green, 1992 ; I will later argue, however, that the
object-directedness of the emotion is only apparent).
By amending and refining the just-described ‘‘basic for-
mula” of the belief–desire analysis of emotions, it is possi-
ble to specify the cognitive and motivational preconditions
of many emotions distinguished in ordinary language (e.g.,
Davis, 1981; Meinong, 1894, 1906; Miceli & Castelfranchi,
2007; Searle, 1983 ). Indeed, there is reason to believe that
all emotions with propositional objects (all emotions directed
at states of affairs) are amenable to a belief–desire analysis.
These emotions cover the vast majority of the emotions dis-
tinguished in ordinary language (see also, Ortony et al.,
1988 ).
1.2. Qualitative belief–desire analysis of emotions
A qualitative belief–desire analysis of some emotions is
shown in Table 1 . To illustrate Table 1 , Mary feels happy
at time t that Schroiber is elected chancellor (= proposition
p), if Mary desires that Schroiber is elected and comes to
firmly believe (i.e., is certain) at t that he was elected. Mary
feels unhappy at t that Schroiber is elected chancellor if she
is aversive to p or ‘‘diswants” p to happen (here analyzed
as: Mary desires not-p, that Schroiber is not elected) and
comes to firmly believe at t that p obtains. Mary hopes at
t that Schroiber is elected chancellor if she wants him to
be elected but is uncertain at t whether or not he will be
Table 1
Belief–desire theory of emotions, qualitative formulation
Emotion if Belief at t Desire at t Belief at t-1
happy (p, t) Certain(p, t) Des(p, t)
unhappy(p, t) Certain(p, t) Des( : p, t)
hopes(p, t) Uncertain(p, t) Des(p, t)
fears(p, t) Uncertain(p, t) Des( : p, t)
surprised(p, t) Certain(p, t) – (irrelevant) Bel( : p, t-1)
disappointed( : p, t) Certain( : p, t) Des(p, t) Bel(p, t-1)
relieved( : p, t) Certain( : p, t) Des( : p, t) Bel(p, t-1)
Notation: Bel(p, t)...believes p at time t; Certain(p, t)...firmly believes p at t
Uncertain(p, t) ¼ : Bel(p, t)& : Certain(p, t)& : Certain( : p, t). Des(p, t)...
desires p at t; Des( : p, t)...desires not-p at t ( is aversive against p at t).
782465562.002.png
R. Reisenzein / Cognitive Systems Research 10 (2009) 6–20
9
1.3. Quantitative formulation of BDTE
ments that have been adduced for cognitive emotion theo-
ries generally (e.g., Ellsworth & Scherer, 2003; Goldie,
2007; Reisenzein et al., 2003 ). Arguments and evidence
more specifically supportive of BDTE stem from two
sources.
First, philosophical proponents of BDTE have argued
that this theory avoids a number of objections raised
against other versions of cognitive emotion theory, espe-
cially cognitive–evaluative or appraisal theories of emotion
(e.g., Green, 1992; Marks, 1982 ; see also, Reisenzein,
2006a ). A central difference between BDTE and the cogni-
tive–evaluative theory of emotion is that the latter regards
emotions as products of factual and evaluative beliefs
rather than of beliefs and desires. To illustrate, whereas
BDTE posits that Mary is happy about p if she believes p
and desires p, the evaluative theory of emotion assumes
that Mary feels happy about p if she believes p and evalu-
ates p as good for herself (i. e., believes that p is good for
her; e.g., Arnold, 1960; Lazarus, 1991 ). Against this
assumption, it has been objected that—even in the presence
of the necessary factual beliefs—evaluative beliefs are not
sucient for emotions. For example, one usually values
being healthy highly; nonetheless, the thought that one is
healthy (factual belief), and that this is good for oneself
(evaluative belief), normally does not cause noticeable
joy. BDTE can easily explain this: At the time of the eval-
uative judgment, the desire to be healthy has long been ful-
filled. It has also been argued that evaluative beliefs are not
generally necessary for emotions. BDTE can handle this
objection, too: To be happy about p, one must desire p
and come to believe that p obtains; it is not necessary that
one in addition believes that p is good for oneself ( Arnold,
1960 ), congruent with one’s motives ( Lazarus, 1991 ), or
goal-conducive ( Scherer, 2001 ).
Second, BDTE is supported by research on the quan-
titative relations between beliefs, desires, and emotions
( Table 2 ). Although studies of this kind are still few in
number and exist only for a few emotions, their results
are generally in line with predictions. For example, Rei-
senzein and Junge (2006) tested several of the ‘‘emotion
laws” shown in Table 2 in a monetary lottery paradigm
(Mellers et al., 1997) . Participants experienced occur-
rences and nonoccurrences of monetary wins and losses
that differed in magnitude and probability and rated
the intensity of experienced surprise, disappointment
and relief caused by each outcome. Support for the pre-
dictions of BDTE was obtained even on the level of indi-
vidual participants. Further supporting the self-reports of
emotions collected by Reisenzein and Junge (2006) ,a
recent fMRI study ( Yacubian et al., 2006 ) found that
unexpected outcomes of a monetary lottery caused
changes in activity proportional to the ‘‘prediction error”
(the difference between the expected and actual outcome
value) in brain regions commonly associated with posi-
tive and negative emotions (the ventral striatum and
the amygdala, respectively) (see also Abler, Walter, Erk,
Kammerer, & Spitzer, 2006 ).
Apart from being able to explain the qualitative (i.e., type)
differentiation of emotions in a parsimonious way, BDTE
also allows a straightforward and parsimonious explanation
of the intensity aspect of emotion (the fact that emotions vary
in intensity). To explain emotional intensity, the qualitative
version of BDTE is refined to a quantitative theory. In fact,
already the first modern formulations of BDTE contained
proposals for a quantification (e.g., Davis, 1981; Day,
1970 ). Quantification is achieved by (a) introducing quantita-
tive concepts of belief and desire and (b) proposing quantita-
tive laws, expressed by numerical functions, that connect
degrees of belief and desire with the intensity of various emo-
tions. Table 2 shows a quantitative belief–desire analysis of
the emotions listed in Table 1 (based mostly on previous pro-
posals; e.g., Davis, 1981; Gratch & Marsella, 2004; Macedo,
Reisenzein, &Cardoso, 2004 ). For example, happiness about
p is experienced when b(p) = 1 and d(p) > 0, and the intensity
of happiness about p is a monotonically increasing function
of d(p). Fear is experienced whenever 0 < b(p)<1 and
d(p) < 0, and the intensity of fear is a monotonically increas-
ing function of j d(p) b(p) j .
1.4. BDTE as a psychological background theory for
computational models of emotion
As a member of the class of cognitive emotion theories,
BDTE is supported by the theoretical and empirical argu-
for domain subset (else emotion
intensity = 0)
Happiness(p, t)=U ha [d(p, t)] b(p, t)=1&d(p, t)>0
Unhappiness(p, t)=U uh [d(p, t)] b(p, t)=1&d(p, t)<0
Hope(p, t)=U ho [b(p, t) d(p, t)] 0 < b(p, t)<1&d(p, t)>0
Fear(p, t)=U fe [b(p, t) d(p, t)]
0 < b(p, t)<1&d(p, t)<0
Surprise(p, t)=U su [b(p, t-1)]
b(p, t)=0&b(p, t-1) > 0
Disappointment( : p, t)=U di [b(p, t-1)
d(p, t-1)]
b(p, t)=0&b(p, t-1) > 0 &
d(p, t-1) > 0
b(p, t)=0&b(p, t-1) > 0 &
d(p, t-1) < 0
Notation: b: p 1 , p 2 , ...} {t 1 , t 2 , ...} ) [0, 1] and
d : f p 1 ; p 2 ; ... gf t 1 ; t 2 ; ... g) R are the belief and desire functions. b(p, t)
represents the strength of belief in p at time t, with 1 denoting certainty that
p, 0.5 maximal uncertainty, and 0 certainty that not-p. d(p, t) represents the
direction and strength of the desire for p at time t, with values > 0 denoting
positive desire, 0 indifference, and values < 0 aversion against p. Happi-
ness(p, t), Unhappiness(p, t) etc. are the emotion intensities, ranging from 0
(absence of the emotion) to some maximumnumber. For arguments outside
the domain subsets indicated in column 2, the value of the emotion func-
tions is 0. Note that the emotion intensity functions (Happiness, Unhappi-
ness etc.) are only partly specified in the table, with U ha , U uh etc. representing
their unspecified components. For example, Gratch andMarsella (2004) use
U = jj (the absolute value function) to be able to represent all emotion
intensities, including those of negative emotions, by positive numbers. If no
further specifications are made, U is the identity function. The functions for
disappointment and relief only capture the case of the simple nonoccurrence
of a desired and undesired event, respectively. For a possible treatment of
the general case see Mellers, Schwartz, Ho, and Ritov (1997) .
Table 2
Belief-desire theory of emotions, quantitative formulation
Emotion Intensity = function
of d and b
Relief( : p, t)=U re [b(p, t-1)
d(p, t-1)]
782465562.003.png
10
R. Reisenzein / Cognitive Systems Research 10 (2009) 6–20
The theoretical and empirical arguments for BDTE sug-
gest that BDTE may be a good choice as a psychological
background theory for computational models of emotion.
Other, more pragmatic considerations support this conclu-
sion. First, BDTE may be more tractable computationally
than are appraisal theories of emotion, as it attributes most
of the multidimensionality and complexity of appraisals to
the objects of the appraisals. As a consequence, much of
the computational labor that appraisal theories of emotion
impose on emotion mechanisms can be relegated to ordin-
ary propositional inference processes ( Reisenzein, 2001 ),
whereas the emotion-generating mechanism proper can
be kept simple. For in contrast to the impression conveyed
by appraisal theories, BDTE suggests that, behind the
apparent complexity of emotions lies a comparatively sim-
ple generating mechanism. This suggestion is borne out by
the computational model of BDTE proposed in the follow-
ing section. Second, the conceptual closeness of BDTE to
the BDI framework should facilitate the integration of
emotions into the BDI architecture (e.g., Becker &
Wachsmuth, 2006; Rank & Petta, 2005; Staller & Petta,
2001 ) and into other computational architectures that have
anities to the BDI approach (e.g., Gratch & Marsella,
2004; Marinier & Laird, 2006 ). Finally, BDTE connects
up naturally with attempts to model emotions in decision
theory (e.g., Mellers, 2000; Zeelenberg, van Dijk,
Manstead, & van der Pligt, 2000 ). This suggests straight-
forward ways of incorporating some effects of emotions
on action into computational models of emotion (see also
Reisenzein, 1996 ; for further discussion).
are controlled by a belief–desire representation system?
That is, in what ways do these agents benefit from having
emotions in addition to beliefs and desires?
The naturalization of BDTE proceeds in three steps. The
first step consists in the modelling of the belief–desire sys-
tem, for beliefs and desires are the causes of emotions in
BDTE. Taking recourse to a strategy proposed by Fodor
(1987) , the belief–desire system is modeled as a proposi-
tional representation system. In the second step, this repre-
sentation system is amended by proposing: (a) The belief–
desire system comes equipped with hardwired mechanisms
that monitor and, if necessary, update the system in
response to newly acquired information. (b) The monitor-
ing mechanisms comprise two submechanisms: One that
compares newly acquired beliefs to existing beliefs and
another that compares newly acquired beliefs to existing
desires. (c) The outputs of these information-processing
mechanisms are ‘‘nonpropositional signals” (in the sense
of Oatley & Johnson- Laird, 1987 ) that carry information
about the degree of match or mismatch of newly acquired
beliefs with existing beliefs and desires. In the third step
(whose description is interwoven with that of the second)
the comparator mechanisms are linked to emotions.
2.1. The representational system
To develop a computational model of BDTE requires to
embrace the assumption that mental and especially cogni-
tive processes are computations in an internal representa-
tion system. I adopt the by now classical representational
assumption of cognitive psychology, that the central repre-
sentation system of humans is symbolic and more precisely,
that it is a language-like, or propositional system of repre-
sentations, a language of thought (e.g., Anderson & Lebi-
ere, 1998; Fodor, 1987; Kintsch, 1988 ). A main reason
for this assumption is that, in contrast to other proposed
representation systems, a propositional system lends itself
naturally to a transparent and plausible computational
analysis of the intentional mental states posited in com-
mon-sense psychology, such as beliefs and desires; and
thereby, to the naturalization of cognitive emotion theories
such as BDTE ( Aydede, 2004; Fodor, 1987; Sterelny, 1991 ;
see also, Gratch & Marsella, 2004 ). 3
How can the naturalization of beliefs and desires be
achieved, given a propositional system of mental represen-
tation? The answer, suggested by Fodor (1987) and others
2. Naturalizing the belief–desire theory of emotion
Like most cognitive emotion theories proposed by phi-
losophers and psychologists, BDTE is formulated on the
‘‘intentional level” of system analysis familiar from com-
mon-sense psychology ( Dennett, 1987 ; see also Reisenzein,
2001; Sterelny, 1991 ). In this section, a proposal is made to
naturalize BDTE, by moving to the ‘‘design level” of the
cognitive system, that is, by sketching a computational
model of BDTE (CBDTE; see also, Reisenzein, 1998,
1999, 2001, 2006b ). Note that my motivation behind this
endeavor was not to develop a worked-out computational
model of emotions, but to use computational thinking
(thinking in terms of representations and computational
mechanisms) as a tool to clarify BDTE and thereby—to
the degree that BDTE is correct as a theory of emotion—
to become clearer about several unresolved issues in emo-
tion psychology. Three aspects of BDTE in particular
needed clarification. First, how (through which cognitive
process) is the causal link between factual beliefs and
desires on the one hand, and emotions on the other hand
(symbolized by the connecting arrows in Fig. 1 ) mediated?
Second, what exactly is the emotion in BDTE; that is, what
is the theoretical definition of emotion in BDTE ( Reisenz-
ein, 2007 )? Third, what are the functions of emotions in
agents whose actions and thoughts, like those of humans,
3 This is of course not meant to deny the existence of other mental
representation systems, such as sensory and image-like representations. In
fact, as explained later, I assume that emotions are nonconceptual,
sensation-like representations. However, imagistic representations as
traditionally conceived of are not suited for representing the contents of
beliefs and desires, as they are not capable of capturing the informational
selectivity and compositional structure of propositions (e.g., Aydede,
2004 ). Although recent imagistic representation systems (the perceptual
symbol systems described in Barsalou, 1999 ) are better suited for this
purpose, this is so precisely because they incorporate central assumptions
of propositional representation systems (see Barsalou, 1999, p. 595 ).
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin