Indo-European_Renfrew - Prehistory Of Languages Xpm.pdf

(729 KB) Pobierz
Renfrew PM
Cambridge Archaeological Journal 10:1 (2000), 7–34
At the Edge of Knowability:
Towards a Prehistory of Languages
Colin Renfrew
The issue of ‘knowability’ in relation to the origins and distribution of the language
families of the world is addressed, and recent advances in historical linguistics and
molecular genetics reviewed. While the much-debated problem of the validity of the
concept of the language ‘macrofamily’ cannot yet be resolved, it is argued that a time depth
for the origins of language families greater than the conventional received figure of c. 6000
years may in some cases be appropriate, allowing the possibility of a correlation between
language dispersals and demographic processes following the end of the Pleistocene
period. The effects of these processes may still be visible in the linguistic ‘spread zones’,
here seen as often the result of farming dispersals, contrasting with the linguistic 'mosaic
zones' whose early origins may sometimes go back to initial colonization episodes during
the late Pleistocene period. If further work in historical linguistics as well as in archaeol-
ogy and molecular genetics upholds these correlations a ‘new synthesis’, whose outlines
may already be discerned, is likely to emerge. This would have important consequences for
prehistoric archaeology, and would be of interest also to historical linguists and molecular
geneticists. If, however, the proposed recognition of such patterning proves illusory the
prospects for ‘knowability’ appear to be less favourable.
T his article, based upon the eleventh McDonald Lec-
ture, 1 is about linguistic diversity and the origins of
the 6500 or so languages spoken in the world today.
These origins may be traced back in some cases over
the past 10,000 or so years. Controversial claims have
been made that some features may be traced back
even further. But the more general question of the
origins of language itself, as a typically human ca-
pacity, will not be discussed, although it is one of the
most fascinating issues in contemporary archaeol-
ogy (Mellars 1998; Pinker 1998). There is a general
consensus (Noble & Davidson 1996) that a fully mod-
ern language capacity is a feature of our species
Homo sapiens sapiens , and that this is likely therefore
to have been the case of our sapiens ancestors of
more than 40,000 years ago, and I do not propose to
consider greater time depths than that. The title of
this article is drawn in part from the current inter-
ests of the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation of New York
on the whole issue of knowability . The question is not
so much about the extent of our current knowledge,
but about the limits to knowledge and the ways by
which we can assess what is in principle knowable,
given favourable conditions of research, and what is
in principle unknowable, being beyond the reach of
human investigation. Some of the research described
here has in part been funded by a generous grant
from the Sloan Foundation applied to the project
‘The Prehistory of Languages’ conducted at the
McDonald Institute.
My own concern for this theme dates back to
my first research in the Aegean and the realization
(Renfrew 1964) that earlier inferences about the chro-
nology of the prehistoric place names of the Aegean
(Haley & Blegen 1928) were invalidated by the dis-
covery of Neolithic settlements on the Cycladic Is-
lands (Evans & Renfrew 1968). This line of reasoning,
applied to the origins of the Greek language, led to a
growing scepticism about the current consensus on
the origins of the Indo-European languages of Eu-
rope (Childe 1926; Gimbutas 1973) that their advent
was due to the activities of warlike nomad pastoralists
7
674656724.002.png
Colin Renfrew
Figure 1. The early spread of agricultural communities
in Europe, as summarized by Stuart Piggott in 1965.
1) Proto-Sesklo and Star ˇ evo cultures; 2) Linear Pottery
culture; 3) Impressed pottery culture. It is suggested
below that the early spread of Proto-Indo-European
speech accompanied the dispersal of farming in these
areas. (From Piggott 1965, 57.)
Figure 2. Radiocarbon chronology (uncalibrated) as
proposed by Grahame Clark in 1965 for the spread of
farming from Anatolia to Europe. Radiocarbon
determinations are shown for the earliest sites of farming
settlements as dated by 1965. The direction and source of
the farming dispersal is very clear. (From Renfrew
1973a, 71.)
from the Pontic steppes. It invited instead the for-
mulation of an alternative theory.
The quest for some radical change in European
prehistory with more convincing explanatory power
than was offered by the alleged coming of the
mounted warrior nomads was influenced by the clear
picture on farming origins outlined for instance by
Piggott (1965, 57, fig. 26) as seen in Figure 1. This
was supported by the striking patterning for the
chronology of the dispersal of farming in Europe
(seen in Fig. 2) established on the basis of radiocar-
bon determinations by Grahame Clark (1965, 46). I
therefore proposed (Renfrew 1973a) that the spread
of farming to Europe from Anatolia was the princi-
pal agency responsible for the arrival and dispersal
of Proto-Indo-European speech. If this proposal were
accepted it would follow that the ‘homeland’ for the
original Proto-Indo-European language would be
situated somewhere in south-central Anatolia (where
James Mellaart had been making striking Early
Neolithic discoveries) and that the arrival of Proto-
Indo-European speech into Europe from Anatolia
could be dated using the available chronology for
the coming of farming to around 7000 BC .
In developing the farming dispersal thesis for
Indo-European into a more comprehensive statement
in Archaeology and Language (Renfrew 1987), I uti-
lized the elegant device proposed by Ammerman &
Cavalli-Sforza (1973) of the ‘wave of advance’ which
modelled the propagation of the farming economy
by a process of ‘demic diffusion’. Although this was
soon criticized by Zvelebil & Zvelebil (1988; 1990) in
its application to the European case, and with some
justice, as an oversimplification, the basic notion of
the arrival of Proto-Indo-European speech in Europe
with the coming of farming has nonetheless been
widely accepted (Zvelebil 1995). At the same time,
the notion of a single Proto-Indo-European dispersal
was seen by many linguists as too simple a hypoth-
esis to account for the complexity of the relation-
ships among the various sub-families of the Indo-
European language family, well illustrated for
instance by Raimo Anttila’s diagram (Anttila 1989)
of isoglosses. Both objections were valid. They are
discussed further below.
In retrospect, then, Archaeology and Language
suffered from two principal defects (among other
deficiencies). In the first place, it laid too much store
by the ‘demic diffusion’ model of Ammerman &
Cavalli-Sforza and not enough on the phenomenon
of contact-induced language change. Ironically per-
haps it is the application of molecular genetics which
has given new insights into the limited extent to
which demic diffusion took place (see below). And
8
674656724.003.png
At the Edge of Knowability
secondly it did not sufficiently deal with the com-
plexity of the further developments of the Indo-Eu-
ropean languages in the long time span after the
initial Proto-Indo-European spread, with local con-
vergence (or advergence) effects responsible for the
formation of some of the sub-families (see now Ren-
frew 1999). But it did, perhaps for the first time in
the context of recent discussions, establish two prin-
ciples or processes which turn out to be applicable
on a much wider canvas than that of prehistoric Eu-
rope. The first is the creation or at least the foundation
of a language family not through some long-distance
tribal migration (like that of the legendary mounted
warrior-nomads) but through a spread phenomenon
which may be seen as the result of an intelligible
economic and demographic process (on the subsist-
ence/demography model). In this case the spread of
farming — a prime case of what Dixon (1997), fol-
lowing Stephen Jay Gould, was later to term a ‘punc-
tuation’, leading to the formation of what Johanna
Nichols (1992) was to name as a linguistic ‘spread zone’.
The second principle is a matter of time depth.
Hitherto, historical linguists have in general come to
employ what the archaeologist would term a ‘short
chronology’, with a time depth for language families
of often just five or six thousand years before the
present. But many of the decisive demographic proc-
esses in world history are climate-related, either the
direct consequence of such phenomena as the end of
the Late Glacial Maximum or the end of the Pleisto-
cene period, or the indirect consequence, dependent
for instance upon the origins of farming, a process
which is now viewed in most parts of the world as
initiated by those climatic events but slower to de-
velop in some areas. By establishing a date as early
as 7000 BC for the first spread of a Proto-Indo-Euro-
pean language (or at least by seeking to do so) it
became possible to view the origins of language fami-
lies within a time-frame linked to the end of the
Pleistocene period which allowed such global
changes to be regarded as relevant to the issue. This
is a principle which, for instance, Nettle (1999a) has
used to very good effect.
It was the publication of Merritt Ruhlen’s very
clear survey A Guide to the World’s Languages (Ruhlen
1991) which opened the way for the employment of
the same principles, using explicit models (Renfrew
1989a) for language change. The wider application
of the language/farming dispersal model, first in
Eurasia (Renfrew 1991) and then much more widely
(Renfrew 1992b; 1996), suggested a global solution
to the problem of the spatial distribution of the
world’s languages, although one which at first
presents a number of problems, particularly linguis-
tic ones. It is noteworthy that over the same period
Peter Bellwood, working in the Pacific, first with the
Polynesian and then with the wider Austronesian
language families, reached similar conclusions on
the relationship between the dispersals of languages
and of agriculture (Bellwood 1989; 1991) in the gen-
esis of language family distributions. He has subse-
quently generalized these to a world level (Bellwood
1996; 1997).
The third strand in this interdisciplinary scene
is the application of molecular genetics, in which
Luca Cavalli-Sforza (Cavalli-Sforza et al. 1988; 1994)
has been a pioneer, and where the pace of new re-
search is extraordinarily rapid. I concluded a review
of these matters in 1991 by predicting the emergence
of a ‘new synthesis’ between historical linguistics,
prehistoric archaeology and molecular genetics (Ren-
frew 1991, 20). These circumstances form the back-
ground to the present enquiry. Matters are made
more interesting by a number of developments in
historical linguistics offering greater insights into
processes of language change. There is also the vexed
question of so-called linguistic phyla or macrofamilies
(such as ‘Nostratic’ and ‘Sino-Caucasian’) which, if
their validity could reliably be established, would
have considerable significance for our understand-
ing of prehistory. For instance, the current distribu-
tions of the languages comprising the constituent
language families of the hypothetical Nostratic
macrofamily (including the Indo-European lan-
guages) could plausibly be explained by the wider
application of the farming/language dispersal model
(Renfrew 1991). But, as we shall see, the current
status of such macrofamilies is problematic. There is
also the potential application of the techniques of
molecular genetics to linguistic problems through
the mediating concept of population demography.
It was in the light of this very complex situation
that it seemed appropriate to use the resources of
the McDonald Institute (whose founder Dr D.M.
McDonald was first led to visit the Department of
Archaeology in Cambridge in 1988 through his in-
terest in the issues raised in Archaeology and Lan-
guage ), and to enlist the support of the Sloan
Foundation to examine some of these problems
through the ‘Prehistory of Languages’ project.
On knowability
At first sight the suggestion of investigating the pre-
history of languages may seem like following a will
o’ the wisp. For if past languages are recorded only
9
674656724.004.png
Colin Renfrew
though the medium of writing, first developed in
western Asia and in Egypt in the fourth millennium
BC and considerably later elsewhere, how could one
hope to consider linguistic events prior to that date?
Fortunately the well-established discipline of his-
torical linguistics can supply at least a partial an-
swer to that question. It does so through the concept
of the language family, established already in 1786
by Sir William Jones (1807). He indicated, with refer-
ence to what is now termed the Indo-European lan-
guage family, that there were a number of related
languages (Greek, Latin, Sanskrit) and sub-families
(Celtic, Germanic) which must be ‘sprung from some
common source’, thereby implying both the notion
of an earlier proto-language (such as Proto-Indo-
European) and an original homeland. Such concepts
are now basic to the discipline of historical linguis-
tics and any history of the discipline will indicate
how the Neogrammarians of the nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries, notably Brugmann, established
the principles of linguistic reconstruction (e.g. Durie
& Ross 1996, ch. 1) with an understanding of regu-
larities in sound change (phonology) and systematic
modifications in word forms and syntax (morphol-
ogy), accompanied by word loss and innovation in
vocabulary (lexical change). The reconstruction of
the hypothetical proto-language can thus be under-
taken, and confidence is gained in the method, for
instance when other languages are discovered which
may be recognized as belonging to the same family
and conforming with comparable principles in their
inferred descent from the reconstructed proto-language.
It is therefore not a vain question to enquire,
using the techniques of archaeology, what material
traces may have been left by the speakers of these
various languages both in the regions where they
are recorded as having been spoken, and in the in-
ferred homeland area. There is a long history of such
researches, not least in the field of Indo-European
studies (Mallory 1973). The matter is of considerable
interest to archaeologists as well as to linguists, since
many archaeological conclusions are based on broad
statements about such issues as the ‘coming of the
Celts’ or the arrival of the first Indo-European speak-
ers (Schrader 1890; Childe 1926). Comparable issues
emerge in every part of the world in relation to the
relevant languages (e.g. McConvell & Evans 1997;
Blench & Spriggs 1997; 1998; 1999a,b).
The relationship between archaeological and
linguistic data has, however, always been a difficult
one. The old equation, established by Childe (1929),
between an archaeological culture, a people and a
language is no longer directly acceptable (Renfrew
1989a). Moreover, while material cultural remains
can be dated with considerable precision by such
techniques as radiocarbon dating, linguistic events
are more difficult to date (Renfrew et al. in press).
And when the data from molecular genetics are
brought into play, the situation becomes even more
complicated (Cavalli-Sforza et al. 1994; Renfrew
1992a).
The matter has become more acute recently with
the postulation of such macrofamilies as ‘Nostratic’
(Dolgopolsky 1998) and ‘Amerind’ (Greenberg 1987)
or indeed ‘Sino-Caucasian’ (Starostin 1989). It is fair
to say that these have been met with scepticism by
the majority of historical linguists. But this has
brought more directly to the fore the question as to
how one should evaluate such proposals. How can
one know?
Of course there is nothing inherently unfamil-
iar in the notion of making verifiable statements about
events in the past which can themselves obviously
no longer directly be observed. Historical linguistics
and prehistoric archaeology are not alone in dealing
with processes and events which are now not di-
rectly observable owing to the passage of time. Such
is the case, of course, with palaeontology and with
cosmology. The relevant deciding test, it is widely
felt, is that which applies to all statements in the
domain of the sciences, namely the Popperian crite-
rion of testability or falsifiability (Bell 1994). But to
say this certainly does not solve the problem, when
it is not clear by what means a particular proposition
may be subjected to testing.
In this field it seems at first sight difficult to
formulate generally applicable criteria (McMahon &
McMahon 1995; Sims-Williams 1998). Certainly there
are cases where a probabilistic approach may be
employed, and where it may validly be asked
whether claims of significant patterning used to sup-
port a hypothesis in fact amount to anything more
than configurations which might equally have arisen
by chance (e.g. Ringe 1996; 1999). But this approach
is more difficult to apply than might at first appear
to be the case. For experience shows that in the de-
velopment of any discipline, new configurations be-
gin to emerge which are not at first clear, and which
are sometimes at first contradicted by counter-exam-
ples. Often it is not easy to formulate the precise
proposition which it is desired to test. One wonders,
for example, whether the statistical tests proposed
by Ringe (1996) would admit Albanian, Armenian,
Tocharian and Sinhalese to the same language fam-
ily, while few linguists today would doubt that all
belong to the Indo-European family.
10
674656724.005.png
At the Edge of Knowability
Sometimes theoretical criteria do not well sup-
ply the answer, and it may transpire that the proof of
the pudding is in the eating. The criteria may then
need subtly to be modified. The task of the Prehis-
tory of Languages project has therefore been to
address a number of current issues, seeking the sup-
port of a body of scholars with a wide range of
opinions, and to see what emerges. The wider aim,
however, must be to establish a number of general
principles relating language change to demographic,
social and economic change. If such principles could
be established and supported by a number of well-
understood cases, they might be of great value in
elucidating other cases which are not yet clear. It is
therefore not simply the falsification (or validation)
procedure which counts: it is also the undertaking of
proposing regularities and hypotheses which are
open to further investigation. Recent developments
in historical linguistics offer hope that this process is
now under way.
tures (such as the presence of head/dependent mark-
ing, dominant alignment, complexity, word order,
voice, etc.) and evaluates the frequencies of such
features in broad geographic areas, claiming to draw
therefrom conclusions about language dispersals go-
ing back to a very much greater time depth, as far as
30,000 years ago. For non-linguists, such as myself,
her work presents difficulties — for the non-initiate
such concepts as ergativity (see Dixon 1994) are tax-
ing — and it is perhaps for that reason that her work
has not been more widely discussed. There is no
doubt, however, that on occasion she makes sweep-
ing assumptions which are certainly open to ques-
tion (e.g. Nichols 1997). For this reason the sustained
criticism by Nettle (1999b) of her views on the date
of the first colonization of the Americas is of particu-
lar interest. However, while some of the historical
assumptions may be dubious, and her historical con-
clusions perhaps should be treated with caution un-
til there has been a fuller evaluation, there is no
doubt that her pioneering approach of population
typology is one of the most interesting developments
of recent years, and one whose further (and perhaps
more cautious) application is likely to bring very
fruitful results.
From the standpoint of the archaeologist, how-
ever, the most promising development in historical
linguistics in recent years is a new willingness among
some linguists to relate linguistic change to changes
taking place also in the material world (the archae-
ologist is almost tempted to say the ‘real world’),
including economic, social and demographic changes.
For too long, in my view, there has been the assump-
tion in some quarters that language changes by its
own rhythms and according to its own rules, quite
independently of demographic or social factors. Sev-
eral recent works have decisively broken that tradi-
tional mould. Among them is Christopher Ehret’s
An African Classical Age (Ehret 1998) where the lin-
guistic history of Africa is related to the social and
economic transformations which have taken place
there over the past ten thousand years or so (al-
though it should be noted that his view of the ori-
gins of the Afroasiatic language family differs
significantly from that recently advanced by Dia-
konoff (1998)).
Perhaps yet more significant, because framed
in more general terms, are two refreshing works
which will perhaps open a new chapter in historical
linguistics, and in particular in the understanding of
linguistic change in relation to demographic and so-
cial change, and hence potentially to the archaeo-
logical record. The first of these is Daniel Nettle’s
Recent developments in historical linguistics
The enhanced level of self-awareness in the field of
historical linguistics is well documented by the spate
of recent overviews or textbooks to complement such
earlier works as those of Hock (1986) and Anttila
(1989), including such useful texts as those of
McMahon (1994), Fox (1995), Lass (1997) and Camp-
bell (1998) and the valuable collected work edited by
Durie & Ross (1996).
More controversial, but of particular interest to
the archaeologist because of the very great time
depths which she contemplates, is Linguistic Diver-
sity in Space and Time by Johanna Nichols (1992).
Here she does not dispute the widely-held view
among historical linguists that genetic (i.e. familial)
relationships cannot, employing the standard com-
parative method, be observed between languages
which became separated more than about 8000 years
ago. As she puts it (Nichols 1992, 313):
Standard comparative method, then, requires
accidence of grammar and such things as shared
arbitrary lexical categorization as evidence for an
initial assumption of relatedness . . . it reconstructs
not only a sound system and a lexicon but also a
grammatical system which is an individual and
not a type. The diagnostic kinds of accidence ap-
parently persist in genetic groups only for a few
millennia, and dissipate entirely after about 8000
years.
Instead she advocates a population typology ap-
proach using what she terms stable structural fea-
11
674656724.001.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin